1 of 55

Introduction to Linguistics:

Semantics & Pragmatics

Masoud Jasbi

LIN001

Week 6

2 of 55

Types of Meaning

Lexical Meaning

single vs. married

Compositional Meaning

break a leg!

Use Meaning

Do you want to stop being annoying?

Social Meaning

pop vs. soda

3 of 55

The Role of Context

We can study the meaning of words, phrases, and sentences within a specific context or independent of context.

Semantics is the study of context-independent aspects of meaning.

Pragmatics studies the effect of context and language use in creating meaning.

4 of 55

Semantics

5 of 55

Subareas of Semantics

Semantics has two main subareas:

  1. Lexical Semantics: the study of what individual words mean.
  2. Compositional Semantics: the study of how words combine to make the meaning of phrases and sentences.

6 of 55

Lexical Semantics

7 of 55

Dictionary Theory of Meaning

Do dictionaries provide the meaning of words?

Is it possible for a robot to learn the meaning of words in a language using a dictionary?

What is missing from a dictionary?

8 of 55

Reference

The referent of an expression is the entity that the expression (currently) refers to.

Joe Biden

Jill Biden’s husband

46th president of the US

The US president

9 of 55

Sense

The sense of an expression is the abstract concept associated with the set of possible referents for that expression.

Joe Biden

Jill Biden’s husband

44th president of the US

The US president

10 of 55

Compositional Semantics

11 of 55

Sentence Meaning

The meaning of a sentence is called a proposition.

A proposition describes a state of affairs.

A proposition can be true or false.

What is truth?

12 of 55

Truth Conditions

To know the meaning of a sentence (i.e proposition), one must know (among other things) the conditions under which it is true.

Which of these are true?

Everyone here is sitting.

Everyone here is a nice person.

13 is a prime number.

How could you know?

13 of 55

Sentence Meaning

The meaning of a sentence (i.e proposition), is (at least) its truth conditions.

Everyone here is sitting” is true iff …

Everyone here is a nice person” is true iff

13 is a prime number” is true iff …

14 of 55

Tautologies and Contradictions

A tautology is a proposition that is always true.

A dollar is a dollar.

Everything either is or is not a taco.

Two propositions are contradictory if they can’t be true at the same time and at least one has to be true.

Remy is a rat.

Remy is not a rat.

15 of 55

Entailment

“P entails Q” means that if P is true, then Q must necessarily be also true.

P = “Remy is a rat.”

Q = “Remy is an animal.”

P ⇒ Q

How about the other way round?

Q ⇏ P

Q

P

16 of 55

Exercise

Determine which propositions entail/contradict each other.

A= Every UCD student has an UCD ID number.

B= Everyone with a UCD ID number is a UCD student.

C= Every LIN1 student has a UCD ID number.

D= Not every UCD student has a UCD ID number.

E= Some UCD students have UCD ID numbers.

F= Most of those with UCD ID numbers are UCD students.

17 of 55

Principle of Compositionality

The meaning of an expression is a function of the meaning of its parts and their mode of combination.

round metal objects

Joe runs

tall meerkats

fake guns

18 of 55

Verb Meaning

We defined the meaning of a proper name as the entity it refers to.

Joe Biden →

We defined the meaning of a sentence as its truth conditions.

“Joe Biden runs” = T/F

What do verbs like run mean?

19 of 55

Verb Meaning

N

Joe

V

runs

Joe runs

S

= T

Joe → T

Abe → F

Bob → F

Barack → T

...

{Joe, Barack...}

20 of 55

Verb Meaning

N

Joe

V

likes

Joe likes Barack

S

= T

Joe → [Joe →T, Abe →F...]

Abe → [Joe →T, Abe →T...]

Bob → [Joe→T, Abe →F...]

...

N

Barack

Joe → T

Barack → T

Abe → F

Bob → F

...

VP

likes Barack

{<Joe, Joe>, <Joe, Barack>, ...}

{Joe, Barack, ...}

21 of 55

Exercise

“Abe” → 😎 “Cleo” → 👸

“Bo” → 👻 “Dana” → 💃

“laughs” → {👻,😎}

“dances” → {👸, 👻, 💃}

“likes” → {<😎,👸>, <😎,👻>,<😎,💃>}

“Emails” → {<😎,👸>,<👸,👻>, <👻,💃>, <💃,😎>}

“Abe laughs.”

“Dana dances.”

“Cleo laughs.”

“Abe likes Bo.”

“Bo emails Dana.”

“Dana emails Bo.”

“Abe likes everyone”

Given the definitions on the left, are the sentences on the right true?

22 of 55

Types of Adjectives

  1. Intersective
  2. Subsective (relative intersective)
  3. Non-subsective (non-intersective)
  4. Privative (anti-intersective)

23 of 55

Intersective Adjectives

An adjective ADJ is intersective iff for all N, ⟦ADJ N⟧ = ⟦ADJ⟧∩⟦N⟧.

In other words when something is [ADJ N], it is both [ADJ] and [N].

Examples: red

Is a [red chair] red?

Is a [red chair] a chair?

Any other examples of intersective adjectives?

red things

chairs

red chairs

24 of 55

Subsective Adjectives

An adjective ADJ is subsective iff, for all N, ⟦ADJ N⟧ ⊆ ⟦N⟧.

Example: skillful

A [skillful violinist] is only skillful as a violinist.

Not for example a surgeon!

Can you think of more examples?

skillful

violinist

25 of 55

Non-subsective Adjectives

An adjective ADJ is non-subsective if there is at least one N such that, ⟦ADJ N⟧ ⊈ ⟦N⟧

Example: alleged

Is an [alleged fraud] an alleged thing?

Is an [alleged fraud] a fraud?

Any other examples?

26 of 55

Privative Adjectives

An ADJ is privative iff for all N, ⟦ADJ N⟧ ∩⟦N⟧ = ∅

Example: fake

Is a [fake gun] a fake thing?

Is a [fake gun] a gun?

Is a [fake ID] fake?

Is a [fake ID] an ID?

Can you think of other examples?

27 of 55

Pragmatics

28 of 55

Types of Meaning

At-issue (ordinary) Entailments

Presupposition

Conversational Implicatures

29 of 55

Presupposition

The of meaning that is assumed or presupposed.

Did you stop smoking?

If the unicorn visits me today, I’ll let you know.

If a unicorn visits me today, I’ll let you know.

Did you see the unicorn?

Did you see a unicorn?

30 of 55

Conversational Implicatures

Conversational Implicatures are meanings that are the result of our reasoning about:

the rules of the conversation

why speakers said what they said

In order to better understand conversational implicatures, we need to know a bit about philosophy of language in mid 20th century.

31 of 55

Formalists vs. Informalist Philosophy

A central question in 20th Century Philosophy was “Is language logical”?

Bob bought beer or wine.

Have some beer or wine!

If you give me the money, I will let you go.

Formalists argued that there are divergences between language and logic. Language is illogical, unsystematic, and unsuitable for science.

Informalists argued there is still value in understanding language. Many types of valid argumentation are only captured by language.

32 of 55

Logic and Conversation

Philosopher Paul Grice argued:

I wish, rather, to maintain that the common assumption of the contestants that the divergences [between language and logic] do in fact exist is (broadly speaking) a common mistake, and the mistake arises from inadequate attention to the nature and importance of the conditions governing conversation.

Paul Grice

Philosopher, UC Berkeley

1931-1988

33 of 55

The Rules of Conversation

Grice argued that linguistic communication follows similar rules to that of rational social interaction generally.

Conversational participants follow the cooperative principle:

Make your conversational contribution such as is required, at the stage at which it occurs, by the accepted purpose or direction of the talk exchange in which you are engaged.”

Paul Grice

Philosopher, UC Berkeley

1931-1988

34 of 55

Gricean Maxims

Maxim of Quality: Try to make your contribution one that is true. Do not say what you believe to be false. Do not say that for which you lack adequate evidence. things for which you lack evidence.

Maxim of Quantity: Make your contribution as informative as required. Do not make your contribution more informative than is required.

Maxim of Relation: Be relevant.

Maxim of Manner: Be perspicuous. Avoid obscurity of expression. Avoid ambiguity. Be brief. Be orderly.

35 of 55

Gricean Reasoning

The cooperative principle and its maxims can be violated or flouted.

They are violated when a speaker simply refuses to abide by them.

They are flouted, when they seem to have been violated, but with additional implications, we can still consider the conversation to have followed them.

These additional implications are called conversational implicatures.

36 of 55

Example

A: Did you buy beer and wine for the party?

B: I bought beer.

A: Why didn’t you buy wine?

37 of 55

Gricean Reasoning

  1. Speaker B said: “I bought beer.”
  2. Speaker B could have said: “I bought beer and wine.”
  3. I bought beer and wine.” is more informative than “I bought beer.”
  4. Assuming that B follows the cooperative principle and the maxim of quantity, they should have said: “I bought beer and wine.” Why didn’t they?
    1. Maybe B is not following the CP and its maxims.
    2. Maybe B did not say “I bought beer and wine.” because it is not true and having said so would have violated the maxim of Quality.
      1. Therefore, it’s true that B bought beer but not that B bought beer and wine.

38 of 55

Example

A: Did you buy beer and wine for the party?

B: I bought beer.

A: Why didn’t you buy wine?

B: I didn’t say I didn’t buy wine.

A: You said you bought beer.

B: Yes. I bought beer.

A: Did you buy wine?

B: Yes.

39 of 55

Example

A: I feel hungry.

B: There is pizza in the fridge.

→ “.. and you can eat the pizza.”

A: It won’t be there for too long.

→ “... because I will eat the pizza.”

B: I’m sure some of it will stay there.

→ “... because you are not allowed to finish it all.”

40 of 55

Example

A: Do you like your car?

B: It’s a car.

Is B cooperative?

If no, what maxim is violated?

If yes, what maxim is flouted? What implicature is generated?

41 of 55

Example

A: I went to bed and brushed my teeth.

→ I first went to bed, then brushed my teeth.

B: In that order?

A: Of course not.

42 of 55

43 of 55

Back to Logical Words

A: I want beer or wine.

  1. The speaker said “I want beer or wine.”
  2. The speaker knows what they want.
  3. If they wanted both, they could have said: “I want beer and wine.”
  4. They did not say that, therefore, they don’t want beer and wine.

44 of 55

Gricean Pragmatics

The cooperative principle and its maxims are like conversational expectations that if flouted, result in inferences on why did the speaker do so.

The addressee comes up with possible reasons and picks the best explanation.

This is in essence abductive reasoning or inference to the best explanation.

An important part of this reasoning is the consideration of what the speaker could have said (alternatives).

45 of 55

Scalar Implicature

How does “some” imply “some but not all”?

Example: some of the students in this class are going to pass.

Implicature: not all are going to pass.

46 of 55

Scalar Implicature

The speaker said “some of the students are going to pass.”

The speaker could have said the stronger alternative “all of the students are going to pass.”

Why didn’t s/he?

→ S/he does not believe all students are going to pass.

47 of 55

Speech Act Theory

48 of 55

Language as Action

Language is a type of action. Saying things is doing things!

assert, question, order, promise, advise, suggest, request, …

In some cases, called performative speech acts, language is the main action.

I throw the ball. (not an act of ball throwing)

I promise to throw the ball. (an act of promising)

Many verbs, called performative verbs, encode such performative acts.

declare, promise, advise, order, …

49 of 55

Felicity Conditions

A speech act is felicitous if it is uttered in the context where the right conditions are met.

To declare two people husband/wife you need to have the right authority.

A promise should be made by the speaker with the intention to keep it.

# My friend hereby promises to give me his car.

50 of 55

Declaring Bankruptcy

51 of 55

Sentence Types

Declarative

This is a class. You should follow the rules. I wonder why.

Interrogative

Is this a class? Should you follow the rules? I wonder why?

Imperative

Be a class! Follow the rules! Wonder why!

Exclamative

What a class! Such terrible rules! Wonderful students!

52 of 55

Speech Act Terminology

The act of saying something is called the locutionary act.

The illocutionary act or the illocution is the intention of the locutionary act.

The perlocution is the actual effect of utterance on the addressee.

Persuading, convincing, scaring, enlightening, inspiring, or otherwise getting someone to do or realize something, whether intended or not (Austin 1962)

53 of 55

Classes of Illocutionary Acts (Searle 1975)

Assertives: commit a speaker to the truth of the expressed proposition

Directives: cause the hearer to take a particular action, e.g. requests, commands and advice

Commissives: commit a speaker to some future action, e.g. promises and oaths

Expressives: express on the speaker's attitudes and emotions towards the proposition, e.g. congratulations, excuses and thanks

Declarations: speech acts that change the reality in accord with the proposition of the declaration, e.g. baptisms, pronouncing someone guilty or pronouncing someone husband and wife

54 of 55

Sentence Type vs. Illocutionary Force

from Chris Potts’ course LING 106A

55 of 55